Evolution - Does Character Count?
Evolutionists try to make everything about human nature a product of an
unguided, naturalistic ancestry. Then why have sermons or seminars on
doing the right thing?
It matters that we
help others: The BBC News asked if it matters that we help others,
launching into the history of George Price and J.B.S. Haldane who “evolved”
altruism as “self-interest in disguise”. Price even wrote an
equation for the evolution of altruism that “underpins a lot of modern
evolutionary biology research” today. Price recognized, though, that
an equation renders compassion meaningless: “If altruism was simply an
attempt to ensure the survival of one’s own genes, could it be considered
altruism at all?” When thinking about that depressed George Price so
much that he turned to Christ and devoted his life to helping others. He
suffered from depression, though, and allegedly committed suicide. The rest of
the article gave views of experts who deny that humans are genetically
determined. They did not address, though, how evolution could explain the
non-biological parts of human nature:
“If we want to understand behavior,
biology is part of it — it has to be by definition. But that’s never an entire
and complete explanation for the complexity and grandeur of the human
condition.” – Oren Harman, biographer of George Price
You can choose not to
indulge: According to Science Daily, “Mindful individuals
[are] less affected by immediate rewards.” What is mindfulness, though,
if not choice to go against one’s natural inclinations?
The Good Samaritan
chose to be compassionate: Live Science asked, “Is being a good
Samaritan a matter of genes?” Richard Dawkins famously advocated the
“selfish gene” theory, describing compassion for members of a group as really
disguised selfishness. Ohio State psychologists stated, “Dawkins’ view fails
to account for the many instances in which humans have helped others to whom
they were not closely related, and have done so with no apparent genetic
benefit to themselves.” The article left the causes of pro-social
behavior a “widely-debated question.”
Even scientists
recognize the need for ethics: Science Magazine praised a program at
the University of Minnesota that helps “Students Propose Genetic Solutions
to Societal Problems.” Their “Essay on Science and Society” says
about the program, “Instructors coach the teams throughout the semester
on experimental design and resources, as well as on data analysis, presentation
strategies, team work, and research ethics.”
Altruism must extend
beyond kinship: In Nature, Daniel Sarewitz wrote an essay entitled, “Science’s
rightful place is in service of society.” Sarewitz writes about “the
public good,” a nebulous category that certainly would extend beyond one’s
immediate evolutionary kin. Sarewitz criticized “the isolation of
the conduct of science from its use in society.” He is appalled when
basic science does not help with economic prosperity, helping the poor find
jobs, etc. He wants science to move “in the right direction — away from
an obsession with how much money is spent on science, and towards a
consideration of how best to ensure that science investments turn into
public value.”
Yet evolutionary
explanations still dominate: In Nature, John Whitfield reviewed two
books that account for human nature as a product of evolution. Whitfield
himself thinks that way:
“Morality is an appetite for certain types of behavior
in oneself and others,” he states. “Like tastes in food and sex, it is rooted
in biology, shaped by culture and imperfectly controlled by reason.” (He
did not explain where reason came from). The first book, Just Babies
by Paul Bloom, treats morality as an instinct (this is supported by an article
in New Scientist that shows newborns can recognize good and evil at an
early age). The second book, Moral Tribes: Emotion, Reason,
and the Gap Between Us and Them by Joshua Greene, also views morality as
the instinctive product of an evolutionary process. Greene, however,
thinks morality arrives as a mimic of the pragmatic philosophy of
utilitarianism (“the greatest happiness for the greatest number”). Argued
using reason by Jeremy Bentham in the 18th century and by John Stuart Mill in
the 19th, utilitarianism is typecast by Greene as the product of an evolutionary
process. In another review of Greene’s book, Thomas Nagel in New
Republic recognizes that a blind process like evolution turns
morality into an illusion:
The most difficult problem posed by
Greene’s proposals is whether we should give up trying to understand our
natural moral intuitions as evidence of a coherent system of individual
rights that limit what may be done even in pursuit of the greater good. Should
we instead come to regard them as we regard optical illusions, recognizing them
as evolutionary products but withholding our assent? Greene’s debunking
arguments add an empirical dimension to a venerable utilitarian tradition, but
they certainly do not settle the question.
Nagel, an atheist, famously denounced Darwinism and opened
the door to intelligent design last year (see Evolution News & Views),
earning himself scorn from other atheists and evolutionists (ENV Dembski, ENV
Klinghoffer). It appears that the explanatory power of Darwinism to account for human
nature is part of his critique. His latest book is called Mind
and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature is Almost
Certainly False.
These articles all skirt the main issue. The evolutionists want to subsume all of
reality into their Darwinian mechanism, turning altruism, morality and
character into epiphenomena of materialism. The others, fearful of
the subjective relativism that would result, cannot bring themselves to embrace
such reductive ideas. Once it dawns on enough people that reason itself cannot be employed to argue the truth of
evolution, Darwinism will be seen for what it is: a self-refuting proposition.
You can’t use reason to argue that reason is an optical illusion! Once
the deck is cleared of such nonsense, those who can account for reason will
remain to employ it in the defense of “a coherent system of individual
rights that limit what may be done even in pursuit of the greater good”
(Nagel). Logic (which sees coherence as a good thing) will further push them to
the realization that rights, to be coherent, must have a Source that is
timeless, universal, and unchangingly righteous. Name One.
No comments:
Post a Comment